El principio de universalización y la razón práctica (2a. parte)
Guariglia, Osvaldo
Instituto de Investigaciones Filosóficas, UNAM, publicado en Crítica. Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía, y cosechado de Revistas UNAM
dor_id: 4115359
506.#.#.a: Público
590.#.#.d: Cada artículo es evaluado mediante una revisión ciega única
510.0.#.a: Arts and Humanities Citation Index, Revistes Cientifiques de Ciencies Socials Humanitais (CARHUS Plus); Latinoamericanas en Ciencias Sociales y Humanidades (CLASE); Directory of Open Access Journals (DOAJ); European Reference Index for the Humanities (ERIH PLUS); Sistema Regional de Información en Línea para Revistas Científicas de América Latina, el Caribe, España y Portugal (Latindex); SCOPUS, Journal Storage (JSTOR); The Philosopher’s Index, Ulrich’s Periodical Directory
561.#.#.u: https://www.filosoficas.unam.mx/
650.#.4.x: Artes y Humanidades
336.#.#.b: article
336.#.#.3: Artículo de Investigación
336.#.#.a: Artículo
351.#.#.6: https://critica.filosoficas.unam.mx/index.php/critica
351.#.#.b: Crítica. Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía
351.#.#.a: Artículos
harvesting_group: RevistasUNAM
270.1.#.p: Revistas UNAM. Dirección General de Publicaciones y Fomento Editorial, UNAM en revistas@unam.mx
590.#.#.c: Open Journal Systems (OJS)
270.#.#.d: MX
270.1.#.d: México
590.#.#.b: Concentrador
883.#.#.u: https://revistas.unam.mx/catalogo/
883.#.#.a: Revistas UNAM
590.#.#.a: Coordinación de Difusión Cultural
883.#.#.1: https://www.publicaciones.unam.mx/
883.#.#.q: Dirección General de Publicaciones y Fomento Editorial
850.#.#.a: Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México
856.4.0.u: https://critica.filosoficas.unam.mx/index.php/critica/article/view/693/671
100.1.#.a: Guariglia, Osvaldo
524.#.#.a: Guariglia, Osvaldo (1989). El principio de universalización y la razón práctica (2a. parte). Crítica. Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía; Vol. 21 Núm. 61, 1989; 3-41. Recuperado de https://repositorio.unam.mx/contenidos/4115359
245.1.0.a: El principio de universalización y la razón práctica (2a. parte)
502.#.#.c: Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México
561.1.#.a: Instituto de Investigaciones Filosóficas, UNAM
264.#.0.c: 1989
264.#.1.c: 2018-12-11
506.1.#.a: La titularidad de los derechos patrimoniales de esta obra pertenece a las instituciones editoras. Su uso se rige por una licencia Creative Commons BY-NC-ND 4.0 Internacional, https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/legalcode.es, para un uso diferente consultar al responsable jurídico del repositorio por medio del correo electrónico alberto@filosoficas.unam.mx
884.#.#.k: https://critica.filosoficas.unam.mx/index.php/critica/article/view/693
001.#.#.#: 034.oai:ojs2.132.248.184.97:article/693
041.#.7.h: spa
520.3.#.a: There is no doubt that one of the issues which have been more discussed about in the contemporary ethics bibliography is that of the universalization principIe and its applications to specific cases, applications which involve sorne universalizability criteria. On discussing the problems for contemporary philosophy derived from this principie, there has been a tendency to intermingle, if not to mix up, the principle itselfwith the universalizability criteria which each author proposes to satisfy it, Opposed to this tendency, we propose to clearly separate the universalization principle from the said criteria, considering that the former provides a logical scheme which constitutes the support, the ultimate warrant, for particular moral judgements. With this procedure we intend to study the structure of such a principIe and the elements that are involved in its forrnulation; only after this examination can we have a more precise idea about what is needed in an universalizability criterion in order to use it without been exposed to strong counterexamples. In this paper I show, first, (I) a scheme of the universalization principIe in order to clarify not only its logical structure but the different concepts that must be specified in each case so that the principIe can be applied significantly. The analysis of all the elements involved in moral discourse —human individuals, different kinds of properties, aetions, obligations and prohibitions— will show to which extent the significative application of the universalization scheme presupposes a dense weave of previous semantic, pragmatic and logico-practic rules, that constitute the first level from which moral judgement afterwards arises. This analysis once completed, I will examine (II) the function of the principle in the field of moral judgements and its main role as ultimate rule of practical reason to which it grants its peculiar form of objectivity. For one concept that has been submerged in a deep crisis within contemporary philosophy is, undoubtedly, the concept of "practical reason". Indeed, while logic and epistemology were contributing with a certain model, in fact more and more discussed but still persistent, of "theoretical reason", what had been considered the traditional field of practical reason: human action, ethics and politics, remained imprisoned within the dilemma of either finding its place again as an object of theoretical study or being thrown forever to the realm of the unpredictable, the arbitrary, in short, the irrational. Briefly, on evaporating, together with the last remainders of philosophy of conscience,the architectural work of the three Critiques, the challenge offered by Hume when he denied all intervention of reason on moral was renewed by quite different courses. The reconstruction of a practical reason , undergone also from different positions and with propositions not always compatible, gathers together, with equal zeal, kantian heritage and its attempt to bring it at Ieast to the same level ofvalidity as reason in its theoretical use. The present paper tries to offer an examination of the irreplaceable contribution of the universalization principle to a reconstructive notion of practical reason as ultimate reason for valid moral judgements.
773.1.#.t: Crítica. Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía; Vol. 21 Núm. 61 (1989); 3-41
773.1.#.o: https://critica.filosoficas.unam.mx/index.php/critica
022.#.#.a: ISSN electrónico: 1870-4905; ISSN impreso: 0011-1503
310.#.#.a: Cuatrimestral
300.#.#.a: Páginas: 3-41
264.#.1.b: Instituto de Investigaciones Filosóficas, UNAM
doi: https://doi.org/10.22201/iifs.18704905e.1989.693
handle: 00d63bc9fbb03fe5
harvesting_date: 2023-08-23 17:00:00.0
856.#.0.q: application/pdf
file_creation_date: 2010-10-09 00:31:18.0
file_modification_date: 2010-10-27 22:32:32.0
file_creator: Claudia Chavez
file_name: 59ee7634d8354a014fa145fdd0607cd7e4977d1320ea75663f9a5e687885cfcf.pdf
file_pages_number: 39
file_format_version: application/pdf; version=1.5
file_size: 415895
245.1.0.b: El principio de universalización y la razón práctica (2a. parte)
last_modified: 2023-08-23 17:00:00
license_url: https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-nc-nd/4.0/legalcode.es
license_type: by-nc-nd
Guariglia, Osvaldo
Instituto de Investigaciones Filosóficas, UNAM, publicado en Crítica. Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía, y cosechado de Revistas UNAM
Guariglia, Osvaldo (1989). El principio de universalización y la razón práctica (2a. parte). Crítica. Revista Hispanoamericana de Filosofía; Vol. 21 Núm. 61, 1989; 3-41. Recuperado de https://repositorio.unam.mx/contenidos/4115359